Great Article on Dobbs Decision. Bodily Autonomy is the heart of the matter.
https://www.nytimes.com/2022/06/26/opinion/dobbs-roe-autonomy.html
Dobbs, Roe and the Myth of ‘Bodily Autonomy’
June 26, 2022, 11:15 a.m. ET
“We
hold that Roe and Casey must be overruled,” the Supreme Court declared on Friday in its majority opinion
in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization. It boggles the mind, really.
The fight over abortion that has raged as long as I can remember has taken a
decisive turn. The broad spectrum of emotions in reaction to this decision —
from outrage to jubilation and everything in between — will be on full display
for weeks and months to come. Our feelings about this decision matter. But it
is also critical that we continue to examine and clarify the merits of the arguments
about abortion.
“Bodily autonomy” has become a chief argument against abortion
restrictions. Referring to abortion restrictions
as “forced birth” is common among abortion rights
advocates. Julie Rikelman, who argued in favor of abortion rights in the Dobbs
oral arguments at the Supreme Court, stated that the right to an abortion is
grounded in “liberty,” which includes the right “to physical autonomy,
including the right to end a pre-viability pregnancy.” The Supreme Court’s decision in Dobbs rightly
rejects the idea that rights to bodily autonomy are expansive and absolute, and
therefore make abortion rights necessary.
Of
course, injustice is often writ large on bodies. And injustice against women in
particular is often manifest as a lack of power over our own bodies. We see
this in myriad ways. A 2021 United Nations report found that nearly half of all women
in 57 developing countries are denied bodily autonomy, with violations
including rape, forced sterilization, virginity testing and female genital
mutilation. In American culture, women’s bodies are often viewed as primarily
valuable only for their sex appeal and beauty. Violence is a constant threat to
women’s bodies, with one in five women experiencing completed or attempted
rape during their lifetime and nearly one in four women experiencing domestic violence. To
have a just society, we must have protection of and safety for female bodies,
and women — like men — need to be able to make decisions about their own
bodies.
Yet
the way we understand and define bodily autonomy has profound implications in
our debates about abortion and in how we understand what justice for women
looks like. The Dobbs Supreme Court decision recognized that there is no
inherent right to abortion that flows from a commitment to liberty or autonomy,
in part because “abortion is fundamentally
different, as both Roe and Casey acknowledged, because it destroys what those decisions
called ‘fetal life’ and what the law now before us describes as an ‘unborn
human being.’”
Here are three ways that I find abortion rights arguments that
appeal to bodily autonomy unpersuasive and ultimately harmful to our
understanding of freedom and what it means to be human:
1.
Bodily autonomy is limited by our obligation to not harm others.
We already recognize in law that there are limits to physical autonomy. One
can’t walk down the street naked, even if one really wants to, or go 75 miles
an hour in a school zone, even if slowing down poses a burden on the driver.
These
limits came up in the Dobbs oral arguments. Twice, Justice Clarence Thomas
brought up a case where a woman was convicted of child neglect for ingesting
harmful illegal drugs while pregnant. The Supreme Court’s majority opinion in
Dobbs addresses this as well, saying that an appeal to
autonomy, “at a high level of generality, could license fundamental rights to
illicit drug use, prostitution, and the like.” Our desires to do as we wish
with our bodies must be respected but they also must be limited by the needs
and rights of others, including those who live inside our own bodies.
2.
The term “autonomy” denies the deep interdependence and limitations of every
human body. One definition of autonomy
is “independence.” But no human has complete bodily autonomy from birth to
death. The natural state of human beings is to be deeply and
irrevocably interdependent on one another. The only reason any of us is alive
today is that someone cared for us as children in the womb and then as infants
and toddlers. Almost all of us, through age or disability or both, will eventually
depend on other human beings — other human bodies — to bathe, dress, feed and
otherwise care for us.
A child in the womb is dependent on a mother for life in a way that
does place a unique burden on a mother. But this burden does not end at birth.
Parenthood — at any stage — is an arduous good. A 1-year-old baby is
dependent on adults for nourishment, protection and care in ways that can be
profoundly burdensome, yet we cannot claim “bodily autonomy” as a reason to
neglect the needs of a 1-year-old. Abortion seems to punish a fetus for its
lack of bodily autonomy and deny the profound reliance that all of us who have
bodies hold.
With
this deep interdependence that we all share come obligations to one another. We
do not always choose the ways our bodies are dependent on others. And we often
do not choose the obligations placed on our lives by others who are dependent
on us. Covid threw in sharp relief ways that our bodies and our bodily health
depend on the choices of other people. I’ve criticized those on the right for casting
a choice about whether to get a Covid vaccine as entirely an individual
decision. This kind of individualistic rhetoric is the very logic of autonomy —
that people can do what they want with their own bodies without regarding their
obligations to others. But human bodies, unlike machines, simply aren’t
autonomous. Our choices about our own bodies impact the bodies around us.
3.
The pressing issue when it comes to abortion is whether championing “bodily
autonomy” requires us to override or undo biological realities. In
the Dobbs oral arguments, Julie Rikelman described what women experience if
they lack access to abortion: “Allowing a state to take control of a woman’s
body and force her to undergo the physical demands, risks and life-altering
consequences of pregnancy is a fundamental deprivation of her liberty.”
But
is restricting abortion the same thing as forced gestation? Is it correct to
compare abortion restrictions to a state “taking control” of a woman’s body and
a deprivation of liberty?
Whatever
one thinks sex is and what it is for — whether a sacred act or a mere
recreational pleasure — all of us can agree that sex is the only human activity
that has the power to create life and that every potentially procreative sexual
act therefore carries some level of risk that pregnancy could occur. (Birth
control significantly lessens this risk but does not entirely take it away
since birth control methods can fail.) Yet, the state does not impose this risk
of producing human life; biology does. Except in the horrible circumstances of
rape or incest, which account for 1 percent of abortions, women and men both
have bodily agency and choices about whether they will have sex and therefore
if they are willing to accept the risk of new life inherent in it.
Our
bodies undeniably place a disproportional burden on women in reproduction.
There is an inescapable asymmetry in male and female bodies when it comes to
making and carrying life. To address the particular difficulty that pregnancy
places on women, we need to hold fathers more responsible through child support
laws. And we need to create a culture that does not shame women for unintended
pregnancies but supports them through pro-women policies like paid parental leave,
access to affordable child care, free health care and other measures. Yet, the state, in the end, cannot
and ought not entirely rescue us from the known realities of human biology.
A
sperm and an egg unite to grow into a human inside the body of a woman. The
state doesn’t force this to happen any more than it forces aging or forces
weight loss from exercise or forces lungs to take in oxygen and release carbon
dioxide.
To
use language of forced gestation or of a state “controlling” women’s bodies is
to portray biology itself as oppressive and halting the natural course of the body
as the liberative role of the state.
For both men and women, bodily autonomy can’t mean that we can do
whatever we want, whenever we want, with our own bodies without natural
consequences or obligations to others. If this is what we mean by “autonomy,”
then no one can champion bodily autonomy without ultimately advocating harm.
I
recently came across a blog post by the literature scholar Alan
Jacobs, describing Simone Weil’s insistence that “if
we need a collective declaration of human rights we also, and perhaps more desperately, need a
declaration of human obligations.”
I
find this beautiful. Speaking as a woman, with a woman’s body, I want safety
and freedom for all women. I want women to be full participants and empowered
leaders in public life. I believe we, as human beings and image bearers of God,
have a right to bodily integrity, protection and liberty.
But
these rights also carry obligations to others, perhaps especially to those
vulnerable bodies that depend on us. This is the heart of the question about
abortion: What are our obligations to one another? We have an obligation to
unborn children. We have an obligation to seek women’s safety and flourishing.
For too long these obligations have been pitted against each other, but they need not be and, to move
forward, we must create a world where they never are.
Tish Harrison Warren (@Tish_H_Warren)
is a priest in the Anglican Church in North America and author of “Prayer in the Night: For Those Who Work or Watch or Weep.”
Labels: Bodily Autonomy, Dobbs Decision, jesuits, pro-life, Roe v Wade